Karl Marx

#PUBLICATION NOTE

This edition of Karl Marx has been prepared and revised for digital publication by the Institute of Marxism-Leninism-Maoism under the Central Committee of the Communist Party in Switzerland on the basis of the edition published in the Collected Works of Lenin, Fourth English Edition, Volume 21, Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1964.

#INTRODUCTION NOTE

This is an article written by Comrade Nikolaj Lenin in July-November 1914. It was first published in the Granat Encyclopaedia, Seventh Edition, Vol. 28 in 1915.

Lenin began working on this article in Poronin, Galicia, Austria-Hungary in July 1914 and finished it in Berne, Switzerland in November 1914. The article was followed by the Supplement, Bibliography of Marxism. Because of tsarist censorship, the editors of the Encyclopaedia omitted two chapters, «Socialism» and «Tactics of the Class Struggle of the Proletariat», and made a number of changes in the text. In 1918, Priboi Publishers published the original article as a separate pamphlet, with a preface written specifically for it by Comrade Lenin, but without the Supplement.


#Workers and oppressed people of the world, unite!

#PREFACE TO THE 1918 RUSSIAN EDITION

#Nikolaj Lenin
#14th of May, 1918

#

This article on Karl Marx, which now appears in a separate printing, was written in 1913 (as far as I can remember) for the Granat Encyclopaedia. A fairly detailed bibliography of literature on Marx, mostly foreign, was appended to the article. This has been omitted in the present edition. The editors of the Encyclopaedia, for their part, have, for censorship reasons, deleted the end of the article on Marx, namely, the section dealing with his revolutionary tactics. Unfortunately, I am unable to reproduce that end, because the draft has remained among my papers somewhere in Cracow or in Switzerland. I only remember that, in the concluding part of the article, I quoted, among other things, the passage from Marx's letter to Engels of the 16th of April, 1856, in which he wrote: «The whole thing in Germany will depend on whether it is possible to back the proletarian revolution by some second edition of the Peasant War, in which case the affair should go swimmingly.»1 That is what our Minoritarians, who have now sunk to utter betrayal of Socialism and to desertion to the bourgeoisie, have failed to understand since 1905.

#N. Lenin
#Moscow
#14th of May, 1918

#Workers and oppressed people of the world, unite!

#KARL MARX

#A BRIEF BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH WITH AN EXPOSITION OF MARXISM

#Nikolaj Lenin
#July-November 1914

#

#1. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH

Marx, Karl, was born on the 5th of May, 1818, in the city of Trier (Rhenish Prussia). His father was a lawyer, a Jew, who, in 1824, adopted Protestantism. The family was well-to-do, cultured, but not revolutionary. After graduating from a high school in Trier, Marx entered the university, first at Bonn and later in Berlin, where he read law, majoring in history and philosophy. He concluded his university course in 1841, submitting a doctoral thesis on the philosophy of Epicurus. At the time, Marx was a Hegelian idealist in his views. In Berlin, he belonged to the circle of «Left-wing Hegelians» (Bruno Bauer and others) who sought to draw atheist and revolutionary conclusions from Hegel's philosophy.

After graduating, Marx moved to Bonn, hoping to become a professor. However, the reactionary policy of the government, which deprived Ludwig Feuerbach of his chair in 1832, refused to allow him to return to the university in 1836, and in 1841 forbade young Professor Bruno Bauer to lecture at Bonn, made Marx abandon the idea of an academic career. Left-wing Hegelian views were making rapid headway in Germany at the time. Ludwig Feuerbach began to criticize theology, particularly after 1836, and turn to materialism, which in 1841 gained the ascendancy in his philosophy (The Essence of Christianity). The year 1843 saw the appearance of his Principles of the Philosophy of the Future. «One must have experienced the liberating effect» of these books «for oneself to get an idea of it», Engels subsequently wrote of these works of Feuerbach's. «Enthusiasm was universal: we were all Feuerbachians for a moment.»2 At that time, some radical bourgeois in the Rhineland, who were in touch with the Left-wing Hegelians, founded, in Cologne, an opposition paper called the Rhenische Zeitung [Rhenish Newspaper] (the first issue appeared on the 1st of January, 1842). Marx and Bruno Bauer were invited to be the chief contributors, and, in October 1842, Marx became editor-in-chief and moved from Bonn to Cologne. The newspaper's revolutionary-democratic trend became more and more pronounced under Marx's editorship, and the government first imposed double and triple censorship on the paper, and then, on the 1st of January, 1843, decided to suppress it. Marx had to resign the editorship before that date, but his resignation did not save the paper, which suspended publication in March 1843. Of the major articles Marx contributed to the Rhenish Newspaper, Engels notes, in addition to those indicated below (see the Bibliography), an article on the condition of peasant wine-growers in the Moselle Valley. Marx's journalistic activities convinced him that he was insufficiently acquainted with political economy, and he zealously set out to study it.

In 1843, Marx married, at Kreuznach, Jenny von Westphalen, a childhood friend he had become engaged to while still a student. His wife came of a reactionary family of the Prussian nobility, her elder brother being Prussia's Minister of the Interior during a most reactionary period — 1850-58. In the autumn of 1843, Marx went to Paris in order to publish a radical journal abroad, together with Arnold Ruge (1802-80; Left-wing Hegelian; in prison in 1825-30; a political exile following 1848; and a Bismarckian after 1866-70). Only one issue of this journal, the Deutsch-Französische Jahrbücher [German-French Yearbooks], appeared; publication was discontinued owing to the difficulty of secretly distributing it in Germany, and to disagreement with Ruge. Marx's articles in this journal showed that he was already a revolutionary, who advocated «ruthless criticism of all that exists»,3 and, in particular, «criticism by weapons»,4 and appealed to the masses and to the proletariat.

In September 1844, Friedrich Engels came to Paris for a few days, and, from that time on, became Marx's closest friend. They both took a most active part in the then seething life of the revolutionary groups in Paris (of particular importance at the time was Proudhon's doctrine, which Marx pulled to pieces in his Poverty of Philosophy, 1847); waging a vigorous struggle against the various doctrines of small-bourgeois Socialism, they worked out the theory and tactics of revolutionary proletarian Socialism, or Communism (Marxism). See Marx's works of this period, 1844-48, in the Bibliography. At the insistent request of the Prussian government, Marx was banished from Paris in 1845, as a dangerous revolutionary. He went to Brussels. In the spring of 1847, Marx and Engels joined an underground propaganda society called the Communist League; they took a prominent part in the League's Second Congress (London, November 1847), at whose request they drew up the celebrated Communist Manifesto, which appeared in February 1848. With the clarity and brilliance of genius, this work outlines a new worldview, consistent materialism, which also embraces the realm of social life; dialectics, as the most comprehensive and profound doctrine of development; the theory of the class struggle and of the world-historic revolutionary role of the proletariat — the creator of a new, communist society.

On the outbreak of the February Revolution of 1848, Marx was banished from Belgium. He returned to Paris, from which, after the March Revolution, he went to Cologne, Germany, where the Neue Rheinische Zeitung [New Rhenish Newspaper] was published from the 1st of June, 1848 to the 19th of May, 1849, with Marx as editor-in-chief. The new theory was splendidly confirmed by the course of the revolutionary events of 1848-49, just as it has been subsequently confirmed by all proletarian and democratic movements in all countries of the world. The victorious counter-revolutionaries first instigated court proceedings against Marx (he was acquitted on the 9th of February, 1849), and then banished him from Germany (16th of May, 1849). First, Marx went to Paris, was again banished after the demonstration of the 13th of June, 1849, and then went to London, where he lived until his death.

His life as a political exile was a very hard one, as the correspondence between Marx and Engels (published in 1913) clearly reveals. Poverty weighed heavily on Marx and his family; had it not been for Engels's constant and selfless financial aid, Marx would not only have been unable to complete Capital, but would have inevitably been crushed by want. Moreover, the prevailing doctrines and trends of small-bourgeois Socialism, and of non-proletarian Socialism in general, forced Marx to wage a continuous and merciless struggle and sometimes to repel the most savage and monstrous personal attacks (Mr. Vogt). Marx, who stood aloof from small groups of political exiles, developed his materialist theory in a number of historical works (see Bibliography), devoting himself mainly to a study of political economy. Marx revolutionized this science (see «The Marxist Doctrine», below) in his A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (1859) and Capital (Vol. 1, 1867).

The revival of the democratic movements in the late 1850s and '60s recalled Marx to practical activity. In 1864 (28th of September), the International Workers' Association — the celebrated First International — was founded in London. Marx was the heart and soul of this organization, and author of its Inaugural Address and of a host of resolutions, declarations, and manifestos. In uniting the labour movement of various countries, striving to channel into joint activity the various forms of non-proletarian, pre-Marxist Socialism (Mazzini, Proudhon, Bakunin, liberal trade-unionism in Britain, Lassallean vacillations to the Right in Germany, and so on), and in combating the theories of all these sects and schools, Marx hammered out a uniform tactic for the proletarian struggle of the working class in the various countries. Following the downfall of the Paris Commune (1871) — of which Marx gave such a profound, clear-cut, brilliant, effective, and revolutionary analysis (The Civil War in France, 1871) — and the Bakuninite-caused split in the International, the latter organization could no longer exist in Europe. After the Hague Congress of the International (1872), Marx had the General Council of the International transferred to New York. The First International had played its historical part, and now made way for a period of a far greater development of the labour movement in all countries in the world, a period in which the movement grew in scope, and mass working-class Socialist Parties in individual national States were formed.

Marx's health was undermined by his strenuous work in the International and his still more strenuous theoretical occupations. He continued work on the refashioning of political economy and on the completion of Capital, for which he collected a mass of new material and studied a number of languages (Russian, for instance). However, sickness prevented him from completing Capital.

His wife died on the 2nd of December, 1881, and, on the 14th of March, 1883, Marx passed away peacefully in his armchair. He lies buried next to his wife at Highgate Cemetery in London. Of Marx's children, some died in childhood in London, when the family were living in destitute circumstances. Three daughters married English and French Socialists: Eleanor Marx-Aveling, Laura Marx-Lafargue, and Jenny Marx-Longuet. The latter's son is a member of the French Socialist Party.

#2. THE MARXIST DOCTRINE

Marxism is the system of Marx's views and teachings. Marx was the genius who continued and consummated the three main ideological currents of the 19th century, as represented by the three most advanced countries of humanity: classical German philosophy, classical English political economy, and French Socialism, combined with French revolutionary doctrines in general. Acknowledged even by his opponents, the remarkable consistency and integrity of Marx's views, whose totality constitutes modern materialism and modern scientific Socialism, as the theory and programme of the working-class movement in all developed countries of the world, make it incumbent on us to present a brief outline of his worldview in general, prior to giving an exposition of the main content of Marxism, namely, Marx's economic doctrine.

#2.1. PHILOSOPHICAL MATERIALISM

Beginning with the years 1844-45, when his views took shape, Marx was a materialist and especially a follower of Ludwig Feuerbach, whose weak points he subsequently saw only in his materialism being insufficiently consistent and comprehensive. To Marx, Feuerbach's historic and «epoch-making» significance lay in his having resolutely broken with Hegel's idealism and in his proclamation of materialism, which already in «the 18th century, and in particular French materialism, was not only a struggle against the existing political institutions and the existing religion and theology; it was just as much [...] against all metaphysics» (in the sense of «wild speculation» as distinct from «sober philosophy»).5 Marx wrote: «To Hegel, the process of thinking, which, under the name of ‹the Idea›, he even transforms into an independent subject, is the demiurgos (the creator, the maker) of the real world [...]. With me, on the contrary, the ideal is nothing else than the material world reflected by the human mind, and translated into forms of thought.»6 In full conformity with this materialist philosophy of Marx's, and expounding it, Friedrich Engels wrote in Anti-Dühring (read by Marx in the manuscript):

The unity of the world does not consist in its being [...]. The real unity of the world consists in its materiality, and this is proved [...] by a long and wearisome development of philosophy and natural science [...].7

Motion is the mode of existence of matter, hence more than a mere property of it. There is no matter without motion, nor could there ever have been [...]. But if the further question is raised what thought and consciousness really are and where they come from, it becomes apparent that they are products of the human brain and that humankind itself is a product of nature, which has developed in and along with its environment; hence it is self-evident that the products of the human brain, being in the last analysis also products of nature, do not contradict the rest of nature's interconnections but are in correspondence with them. [...]

Hegel was an idealist. To him the thoughts within his brain were to him not the more or less abstract pictures [Abbilder, reflections; Engels sometimes speaks of ‹imprints›] of actual things and processes, but, conversely, things and their evolution were only the realised pictures of the ‹Idea› existing somewhere from eternity before the world was.7

In his Ludwig Feuerbach — which expounded his own and Marx's views on Feuerbach's philosophy, and was sent to the printers after he had reread an old manuscript Marx and himself has written in 1844-45 on Hegel, Feuerbach, and the materialist conception of history — Engels wrote:

The great basic question of all, especially of latter-day, philosophy, is that concerning the relation of thinking and being [...] of the mind to nature [...] which is primary, mind or nature [...]. Answers to this question split the philosophers into two great camps. Those who asserted the primacy of the mind over nature and, therefore, in the last instance, assumed world creation in some form or other [...] comprised the camp of idealism. The others, who regarded nature as primary, belong to the various schools of materialism.

Any other use of the concepts of (philosophical) idealism and materialism leads only to confusion. Marx decidedly rejected, not only idealism, which is always linked in one way or another with religion, but also the views — especially widespread in our day — of Hume and Kant, agnosticism, criticism, and positivism in their various forms; he considered that philosophy a «reactionary» concession to idealism, and, at best, a «shamefaced way of surreptitiously accepting materialism, while denying it before the world».2 On this question, see, besides the works by Engels and Marx mentioned above, a letter Marx to wrote to Engels on the 12th of December, 1868, in which, referring to an utterance by the naturalist Thomas Huxley which was «more materialist»8 than usual, and to his recognition that, «as long as we actually observe and think, we cannot possibly get away from materialism», Marx reproached Huxley for leaving a «loophole»8 for agnosticism, for Humeism. It is particularly important to note Marx's view on the relation between freedom and necessity: «To him, freedom is the insight into necessity [die Einsicht in die Notwendigkeit]. ‹Necessity is blind only in so far as it is not understood [begriffen].›»7 This means recognition of the rule of objective laws in nature and of the dialectical transformation of necessity into freedom (in the same manner as the transformation of the unknown but knowable «thing-in-itself» into the «thing-for-us», of the «essence of things» into «phenomena»). Marx and Engels considered that the «old» materialism, including that of Feuerbach (and still more the «vulgar» materialism of Büchner, Vogt, and Moleschott), contained the following major shortcomings:

  • Firstly, this materialism was «predominantly mechanical»,9 failing to take account of the latest developments in chemistry and biology (today, it would be necessary to add: and in the electrical theory of matter).
  • Secondly, the old materialism was non-historical and non-dialectical (metaphysical, in the meaning of anti-dialectical), and did not adhere consistently and comprehensively to the standpoint of development.
  • Thirdly, it regarded the «human essence» in the abstract, not as the «complex of all» (concretely and historically determined) «social relations», and therefore merely «interpreted» the world, whereas it was a question of «changing» it, that is, it did not understand the importance of «‹revolutionary›, of ‹practical-critical›, activity».9

#2.2. DIALECTICS

As the most comprehensive and profound doctrine of development, and the richest in content, Hegelian dialectics was considered by Marx and Engels the greatest achievement of classical German philosophy. They thought that any other formulation of the principle of development, of evolution, was one-sided and poor in content, and could only distort and mutilate the actual course of development (which often proceeds by leaps, and via catastrophes and revolutions) in nature and in society. Engels writes:

Marx and I were pretty well the only people to rescue conscious dialectics [from the destruction of idealism, including Hegelianism] and apply it in the materialist conception of nature [...].10

Nature is the proof of dialectics, and it must be said for modern science that it has furnished this proof with very rich [this was written before the discovery of radium, electrons, the transmutation of elements, and so on!] materials increasing daily, and has thus has shown that, in the last resort, nature works dialectically and not metaphysically.7

«The great basic thought that the world is not to be comprehended as a complex of ready-made things, but as a complex of processes, in which the apparently stable things, no less than their mental images in our heads, the concepts, go through uninterrupted change of coming into being and passing away [...] this great fundamental thought has, especially since the time of Hegel, so thoroughly permeated ordinary consciousness that in this generality it is now scarcely ever contradicted. But to acknowledge this fundamental thought in words and to apply it in reality in detail to each domain of investigation are two different things [...]. Against it [dialectical philosophy] nothing is final, absolute, sacred. It reveals the transitory character of everything and in everything; nothing can endure against it except the uninterrupted process of becoming and passing away, of ascending without end from the lower to the higher. And dialectical philosophy itself is nothing more than the mere reflection of this process in the thinking brain.2

Thus, according to Marx, dialectics is «the science of the general laws of motion, both of the external world and of human thinking».2

This revolutionary aspect of Hegel's philosophy was adopted and developed further by Marx. Dialectical materialism «no longer needs any philosophy standing above the other sciences».7 From previous philosophy, there remains «the science of thought and its laws — formal logic and dialectics».7 Dialectics, as understood by Marx, and also in conformity with Hegel, includes what is now called the theory of knowledge, or epistemology, which, too, must regard its subject matter historically, studying and generalizing the origin and development of knowledge, the transition from non-knowledge to knowledge.

In our times, the idea of development, of evolution, has almost completely penetrated social consciousness, only in other ways, and not through Hegelian philosophy. Still, this idea, as formulated by Marx and Engels on the basis of Hegel's philosophy, is far more comprehensive and far richer in content than the current idea of evolution is. A development that repeats, as it were, stages that have already been passed, but repeats them in a different way, on a higher basis («the negation of the negation»), a development, so to speak, that proceeds in spirals, not in a straight line; a development by leaps, catastrophes, and revolutions; «breaks in continuity»; the transformation of quantity into quality; inner impulses toward development, imparted by the contradiction and conflict of the various forces and tendencies acting on a given body, or within a given phenomenon, or within a given society; the interdependence and the closest and indissoluble connection between all aspects of any phenomenon (history constantly revealing ever new aspects), a connection that provides a uniform and universal process of motion, one that follows definite laws — these are some of the features of dialectics as a doctrine of development that is richer than the conventional one. (See Marx's letter to Engels of the 8th of January, 1868, in which he ridicules Stein's «wooden trichotomies»,11 which it would be absurd to confuse with materialist dialectics.)

#2.3. THE MATERIALIST CONCEPTION OF HISTORY

A realization of the inconsistency, incompleteness, and one-sidedness of the old materialism convinced Marx of the necessity of «bringing the science of society [...] into harmony with the materialist foundation, and of reconstructing it thereupon».2 Since materialism in general explains consciousness as the outcome of being, and not conversely, then materialist as applied to human social life has to explain social consciousness as the outcome of social being. Marx writes: «Technology discloses man's mode of dealing with Nature, the process of production by which, he sustains his life, and thereby also lays bare the mode of formation of his social relations, and of the mental conceptions that flow from them.»12 In the preface to his A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, Marx gives an integral formulation of the fundamental principles of materialism as applied to human society and its history, in the following words:

In the social production of their existence, men inevitably enter into definite relations, which are independent of their will, namely relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the development of their material forces of production.

The totality of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of production of material life conditions the general process of social, political and intellectual life. It is not the consciousness of men that determines their existence, but their social existence that determines their consciousness. At a certain stage of development, the material productive forces of society come into conflict with the existing relations of production or — this merely expresses the same thing in legal terms — with the property relations within the framework of which they have operated hitherto. From forms of development of the productive forces these relations turn into their fetters. Then begins an era of social revolution. The changes in the economic foundation lead sooner or later to the transformation of the whole immense superstructure. In studying such transformations it is always necessary to distinguish between the material transformation of the economic conditions of production, which can be determined with the precision of natural science, and the legal, political, religious, artistic or philosophic — in short, ideological forms in which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out.

Just as one does not judge an individual by what they think about themself, so one cannot judge such a period of transformation by its consciousness, but, on the contrary, this consciousness must be explained from the contradictions of material life, from the conflict existing between the social forces of production and the relations of production [...]. In broad outline, the Asiatic, ancient, feudal and modern bourgeois modes of production may be designated as epochs marking progress in the economic development of society.13

(See Marx's brief formulation in a letter to Engels dated the 7th of July, 1866: «Our theory that the organization of labour is determined by the means of production.»14)

The discovery of the materialist conception of history, or, more correctly, the consistent continuation and extension of materialism into the domain of social phenomena, removed the two chief shortcomings in earlier historical theories. In the first place, the latter at best examined only the ideological motives in the historical activities of human beings without investigating the origins of those motives, or ascertaining the objective laws governing the development of the system of social relations, or seeing the roots of these relations in the degree of development reached by material production; in the second place, the earlier theories did not embrace the activities of the masses of the population, whereas historical materialism made it possible, for the first time, to study with scientific accuracy the social conditions of the life of the masses, and the changes in those conditions. At best, pre-Marxist «sociology» and historiography brought forward an accumulation of raw facts, collected at random, and a description of individual aspects of the historical process. By examining the totality of opposing tendencies, by reducing them to precisely definable conditions of life and production of the various classes of society, by discarding subjectivism and arbitrariness in the choice of a particular «dominant» idea or in its interpretation, and by revealing that, without exception, all ideas and all the various tendencies stem from the condition of the material productive forces, Marxism indicated the way to an all-embracing and comprehensive study of the process of the rise, development, and decline of socio-economic systems. People make their own history, but what determines the motives of people, of the masses of the people, that is, what gives rise to the clash of conflicting ideas and strivings? What is the sum total of all these clashes in the mass of human societies? What are the objective conditions of production or material life that form the basis of all human historical activity? What is the law of development of these conditions? To all these, Marx drew attention and indicated the way to a scientific study of history as a single process, which, with all its immense variety and contradictoriness, is governed by definite laws.

#2.4. THE CLASS STRUGGLE

It is common knowledge that, in any given society, the strivings of some of its members conflict with the strivings of others, that social life is full of contradictions, and that history reveals a struggle between nations and societies, as well as within nations and societies, and, besides, an alternation of periods of revolution and reaction, peace and war, stagnation and rapid progress or decline. Marxism has provided the guidance, that is, the theory of the class struggle, for the discovery of the laws governing this seeming maze and chaos. It is only a study of the sum of the strivings of all the members of a given society or group of societies that can lead to a scientific definition of the result of those strivings. Now, the conflicting strivings stem from the difference in the position and mode of life of the classes into which each society is divided. «The history of all hitherto existing society is the history of class struggles»,15 Marx wrote in the Communist Manifesto (with the exception of the history of primitive communalism, Engels added subsequently). «Freeperson and slave, patrician and plebeian, lord and serf, guildmaster and journeyperson, in a word, oppressor and oppressed, stood in constant opposition to one another, carried on an uninterrupted, now hidden, now open fight, a fight that each time ended, either in a revolutionary reconstitution of society at large, or in the common ruin of the contending classes [...]. The modern bourgeois society that has sprouted from the ruins of feudal society has not done away with class antagonisms. It has but established new classes, new conditions of oppression, new forms of struggle in place of the old ones. Our epoch, the epoch of the bourgeoisie, possesses, however, this distinctive feature: it has simplified the class antagonisms. Society as a whole is more and more splitting up into two great hostile camps, into two great classes directly facing each other: bourgeoisie and proletariat.»15 Ever since the Great French Revolution, European history has, in a number of countries, tellingly revealed what actually lies at the bottom of events — the struggle of classes. The Restoration Period in France already produced a number of historians (Thierry, Guizot, Mignet, and Thiers), who, in summing up what was taking place, were obliged to admit that the class struggle was the key to all French history. The modern period — that of the complete victory of the bourgeoisie, representative institutions, extensive (if not universal) suffrage, a cheap daily press that is widely circulated among the masses, and so on, a period of powerful and ever-expanding unions of workers and unions of employers, and so on — has shown even more strikingly (though sometimes in a very one-sided, «peaceful», and «constitutional» form) the class struggle as the mainspring of events. The following passage from Marx's Communist Manifesto will show us what Marx demanded of social science as regards an objective analysis of the position of each class in modern society, with reference to an analysis of the conditions of development of each class:

Of all the classes that stand face to face with the bourgeoisie today, the proletariat alone is a really revolutionary class. The other classes decay and finally disappear in the face of modern industry; the proletariat is its special and essential product. The lower middle class, the small manufacturer, the shopkeeper, the artisan, the peasant, all these fight against the bourgeoisie, to save from extinction their existence as fractions of the middle class. They are therefore not revolutionary, but conservative. Nay more, they are reactionary, for they try to roll back the wheel of history. If by chance they are revolutionary, they are so only in view of their impending transfer into the proletariat; they thus defend not their present, but their future interests, they desert their own standpoint to place themselves at that of the proletariat.13

In a number of brilliant works (see Bibliography), Marx gave brilliant and profound examples of materialist historiography, of an analysis of the position of each individual class, and sometimes of various groups or strata within a class, showing plainly why and how «every class struggle is a political struggle».2 The above-quoted passage is an illustration of what a complex network of social relations and transitional stages from one class to another, from the past to the future, was analysed by Marx, so as to determine the result of historical development.

Marx's economic doctrine is the most profound, comprehensive, and detailed confirmation and application of his theory.

#3. MARX'S ECONOMIC DOCTRINE

«It is the ultimate aim of this work to lay bare the economic law of motion of modern society»,16 that is, capitalist, bourgeois society, says Marx in the preface to Capital. An investigation into the relations of production in a given, historically defined society, in their inception, development, and decline — such is the content of Marx's economic doctrine. In capitalist society, the production of commodities is predominant, and Marx's analysis therefore begins with an analysis of the commodity.

#3.1. VALUE

A commodity is, in the first place, a thing that satisfies a human want; in the second place, it is a thing that can be exchanged for another thing. The utility of a thing makes it a use-value. Exchange-value (or, simply, value) is first of all the ratio, the proportion, in which a certain number of use-values of one kind can be exchanged for a certain number of use-vales of another kind. Daily experience shows us that millions upon millions of such exchanges are constantly equating with one another every kind of use-value, even the most diverse and incomparable. Now, what is there in common between these various things, things constantly equated with one another in a definite system of social relations? Their common feature is that they are products of labour. In exchanging products, people equate the most diverse kinds of labour. The production of commodities is a system of social relations in which individual producers create diverse products (the social division of labour), and in which all these products are equated to one another in the process of exchange. Consequently, what is common to all commodities is not the concrete labour of a definite branch of production, not labour of one particular kind, but abstract human labour — human labour in general. All the labour-power of a given society, as represented in the sum total of the values of all commodities, is one and the same human labour-power. Billions upon billions of acts of exchange prove this. Consequently, each particular commodity represents only a certain share of the socially necessary labour-time. The magnitude of value is determined by the amount of socially necessary labour, or by the labour-time that is socially necessary for the production of a given commodity, of a given use-value. «Whenever, by an exchange, we equate as values our different products, by that very act, we also equate, as human labour, the different kinds of labour expended on them. We are not aware of this, nevertheless we do it.»12 As one of the earlier economists said, value is a relation between two persons; only he should have added: a relation concealed beneath a material wrapping. We can understand what value is only when we consider it from the standpoint of the system of social relations of production in a particular historical type of society, moreover, of relations that manifest themselves in the mass phenomenon of exchange, a phenomenon which repeats itself thousands upon thousands of times. «As values, all commodities are only definite masses of congealed labour-time.»12 After making a detailed analysis of the two-fold character of the labour incorporated in commodities, Marx goes on to analyse the form of value and money. Here, Marx's main task is to study the origin of the money-form of value, to study the historical process of the development of exchange, beginning with individual and incidental acts of exchange (the «elementary or accidental form of value»,12 in which a given quantity of one commodity is exchanged for a given quantity of another), passing on to the universal form of value, in which a number of different commodities are exchanged for one and the same particular commodity, and ending with the money-form of value, when gold becomes that particular commodity, the universal equivalent. As the highest product of the development of exchange and commodity production, money masks, conceals, the social character of all individual labour, the social link between individual producers united by the market. Marx analyses the various functions of money in very great detail; it is important to note here in particular (as in the opening chapters of Capital in general) that what seems to be an abstract and at times purely deductive mode of exposition deals in reality with a gigantic collection of factual material on the history of the development of exchange and commodity production.

If we consider money, its existence implies a definite stage in the exchange of commodities. The particular functions of money which it performs, either as the mere equivalent of commodities, or as means of circulation, or means of payment, as hoard or as universal money, point, according to the extent and relative preponderance of the one function or the other, to very different stages in the process of social production.12

#3.2. SURPLUS-VALUE

At a certain stage in the development of commodity production, money becomes transformed into capital. The formula of commodity circulation was {M→C→M} (commodity → money → commodity), that is, the sale of one commodity for the purpose of buying another. The general formula of capital, on the contrary, is {M→C→M}, that is, purchase for the purpose of selling (at a profit). The increase over the original value of the money that is put into circulation is called by Marx surplus-value. The fact of this «growth» of money in capitalist circulation is common knowledge. Indeed, it is this «growth» which transforms money into capital, as a special and historically determined social relation of production. Surplus-value cannot arise out of commodity circulation, for the latter knows only the exchange of equivalents; neither can it arise out of price increases, for the mutual losses and gains of buyers and sellers would equalize on another, whereas what we have here is not an individual phenomenon, but a mass, average, and social phenomenon. To obtain surplus-value, the owner of money «must [...] find [...] in the market a commodity, whose use-value possesses the peculiar property of being a source of value»7 — a commodity whose process of consumption is, at the same time, a process of the creation of value. Such a commodity exists — human labour-power. Its consumption is labour, and labour creates value. The owner of money buys labour-power at its value, which, like the value of every other commodity, is determined by the socially necessary labour-time required for its production (that is, the cost of maintaining the worker and their family). Having bought labour-power, the owner of money is entitled to use it, that is, to set it to work for a whole day — 12 hours, let us say. Yet, in the course of six hours («necessary» labour-time), the worker creates product sufficient to cover the cost of their own maintenance; in the course of the next six hours («surplus» labour-time), they create «surplus» product, or surplus-value, for which the capitalist does not pay. Therefore, from the standpoint of the process of production, two parts must be distinguished in capital: constant capital, which is expended on means of production (machinery, tools, raw materials, and so on), whose value, without any change, is transferred (immediately or part by part) to the finished product; secondly, variable capital, which is expended on labour-power. The value of this latter capital is not invariable, but grows in the labour process, creating surplus-value. Therefore, to express the degree of capital's exploitation of labour-power, surplus-value must be compared, not with the entire capital, but only with the variable capital. Thus, in the example just given, the rate of surplus-value, as Marx calls this ratio, will be 6:6, that is, 100%.

There were two historical prerequisites for capital to arise: firstly, the accumulation of certain sums of money in the hands of individuals under conditions of a relatively high level of development of commodity production in general; secondly, the existence of a worker who is «free» in a double sense: free of all constraint or restriction on the sale of their labour-power, and freed from the land and all means of production in general, a free and unattached labourer, a «proletarian», who cannot subsist except by selling their labour-power.

There are two main ways of increasing surplus-value: lengthening the workday («absolute surplus-value»), and reducing the necessary workday («relative surplus-value»). In analysing the former, Marx gives a most impressive picture of the struggle of the working class for a shorter workday and of interference by the State authority to lengthen the workday (from the 14th to the 17th century) and to reduce it (factory legislation in the 19th century). Since the appearance of Capital, the history of the working-class movement in all developed countries of the world has provided a wealth of new facts amplifying this picture.

Analysing the production of relative surplus-value, Marx investigates the three fundamental historical stages in the capitalist increase of the productivity of labour:

  • Firstly, simple cooperation.
  • Secondly, the division of labour and manufacture.
  • Thirdly, machinery and modern industry.

How profoundly Marx has here revealed the fundamental and typical features of capitalist development is shown incidentally by the fact that investigations into the handicraft industries of Russia furnish abundant material illustrating the first two of the mentioned stages. The revolutionizing effect of large-scale machine industry, as described by Marx in 1867, has revealed itself in a number of «new» countries (Russia, Japan, and so on), in the course of the half-century that has since elapsed.

#3.3. ACCUMULATION OF CAPITAL

To continue. New and important in the highest degree is Marx's analysis of the accumulation of capital, that is, the transformation of a part of surplus-value into capital, and its use, not for satisfying the personal needs or whims of the capitalist, but for new production. Marx revealed the error made by all earlier classical political economists (beginning with Adam Smith), who assumed that the entire surplus-value, which is transformed into capital, goes to form variable capital. In actual fact, it is divided into means of production and variable capital. Of tremendous importance to the process of development of capitalism and its transformation into socialism is the more rapid growth of the constant capital share (of the total capital) as compared with the variable capital share.

By speeding up the supplanting of workers by machinery and by creating wealth at one extreme and poverty at the other, the accumulation of capital also gives rise to what is called the «reserve army of labour», to the «relative surplus» of workers, or «capitalist overpopulation», which assumes the most diverse forms and enables capital to expand production extremely rapidly. In conjunction with credit facilities and the accumulation of capital in the form of means of production, this, incidentally, is the key to an understanding of the crises of overproduction which occur periodically in capitalist countries — at first at an average of every ten years, and later at more lengthy and less definite intervals. From the accumulation of capital under capitalism, we should distinguish what is known as primitive accumulation: the forcible divorcement of the worker from the means of production, the driving of the peasants off the land, the theft of communal lands, the system of colonies and national debts, protective tariffs, and the like. «Primitive accumulation» creates the «free» proletarian at one extreme, and the owner of money, the capitalist, at the other.

#3.4. THE HISTORICAL TENDENCY OF CAPITALIST ACCUMULATION

The «historical tendency of capitalist accumulation» is described by Marx in the following celebrated words:

The expropriation of the immediate producers was accomplished with merciless vandalism, and under the stimulus of passions the most infamous, the most sordid, the pettiest, the most meanly odious. Self-earned private property [of the peasant and handicraftsperson] that is based, so to say, on the fusing together of the isolated, independent labouring individual with the conditions of their labour, is supplanted by capitalist private property, which rests on exploitation of the nominally free labour of others [...].

That which is now to be expropriated is no longer the labourer working for themself, but the capitalist exploiting many labourers. This expropriation is accomplished by the action of the immanent laws of capitalist production itself, by the centralization of capital. One capitalist always kills many. Hand in hand with this centralization, or this expropriation of many capitalists by few, develop, on an ever-extending scale, the cooperative form of the labour process, the conscious technical application of science, the methodical cultivation of the soil, the transformation of the instruments of labour into instruments of labour only usable in common, the economizing of all means of production by their use as means of production of combined, socialized labour, the entanglement of all peoples in the net of the world market, and with this, the international character of the capitalist regime. Along with the constantly diminishing number of the magnates of capital, who usurp and monopolize all advantages of this process of transformation, grows the mass of misery, oppression, slavery, degradation, exploitation; but with this too grows the revolt of the working class, a class always increasing in numbers, and disciplined, united, organized by the very mechanism of the process of capitalist production itself. The monopoly of capital becomes a fetter upon the mode of production, which has sprung up and flourished along with, and under it. Centralization of the means of production and socialization of labour at last reach a point where they become incompatible with their capitalist integument. This integument is burst asunder. The knell of capitalist private property sounds. The expropriators are expropriated.12

#3.5. AVERAGE RATE OF PROFIT

Also new and important in the highest degree is the analysis Marx gives, in Volume 2 of Capital, of the reproduction of aggregate social capital. Here, too, Marx deals, not with an individual phenomenon, but with a mass phenomenon; not with a fractional part of the economy of society, but with that economy as a whole. Correcting the aforementioned error of the classical economists, Marx divides the whole of social production into two big sections:

  • Firstly, production of the means of production.
  • Secondly, production of articles of consumption.

He examines in detail, with numerical examples, the circulation of the aggregate social capital — both when reproduced in its former dimensions and in the case of accumulation. Volume 3 of Capital solves the problem of how the average rate of profit is formed on the basis of the law of value. The immense stride forward made by economic science in the person of Marx consists in his having conducted an analysis, from the standpoint of mass economic phenomena, of the social economy as a whole, not from the standpoint of individual cases or of the external and superficial aspects of competition, to which vulgar political economy and the modern «theory of marginal utility» frequently restrict themselves. Marx first analyses the origin of surplus-value, and then goes on to consider its division into profit, interest, and ground rent. Profit is the ratio between surplus-value and the total capital invested in an undertaking. Capital with a «high organic composition» (that is, with a preponderance of constant capital over variable capital in excess of the social average) yields a rate of profit below the average; capital with a «low organic composition» yields a rate of profit above the average. Competition among capitalists, and their freedom to transfer their capital from one branch to another, will, in both cases, reduce the rate of profit to the average. The sum total of the values of all the commodities in a given society coincides with the sum total of the prices of the commodities, but, in individual undertakings and branches of production, as a result of competition, commodities are sold, not at their values, but at the prices of production (or production prices), which are equal to the capital expended plus the average profit.

In this way, the well-known and irrefutable fact of the divergence between prices and values and of the equalization of profits is fully explained by Marx on the basis of the law of value, since the sum total of values of all commodities coincides with the sum total of prices. However, the equating of (social) value to (individual) prices does not take place simply and directly, but in a very complex way. It is quite natural that, in a society of separate producers of commodities, who are united only by the market, a conformity to law can be only an average, social, mass manifestation, with individual deviations in either direction mutually compensating one another.

A rise in the productivity of labour implies a more rapid growth of constant capital as compared with variable capital. Inasmuch as surplus-value is a function of variable capital alone, it is obvious that the rate of profit (the ratio of surplus-value to the whole capital, not to its variable part alone) tends to fall. Marx makes a detailed analysis of this tendency and of a number of circumstances that conceal or counteract it.

#3.6. THEORY OF GROUND RENT

Without pausing to deal with the extremely interesting sections of Volume 3 of Capital devoted to usurer's capital, commercial capital, and money capital, we must pass on to the most important section — the theory of ground rent. Since the area of land is limited and, in capitalist countries, the land is all held by individual private owners, the price of production of agricultural produce is determined by the cost of production, not on soil of average quality, but on the worst soil; not under average conditions, but under the worst conditions of delivery of products to the market. The difference between this price and the price of production on better soil (or in better conditions) constitutes differential rent. Analysing this in detail, and showing how it arises out of the difference in fertility of different plots of land, and out of the difference in the amount of capital invested in land, Marx fully reveals (see also Theories of Surplus Value, in which the criticism of Rodbertus is most noteworthy) the error of Ricardo, who considered that differential rent is derived only when there is a successive transition from better land to worse. On the contrary, there may be inverse transitions, land may pass from one category into others (owing to advances in agricultural techniques, the growth of towns, and so on), and the notorious «law of diminishing returns», which charges nature with the defects, limitations, and contradictions of capitalism, is profoundly erroneous. Further, the equalization of profit in all branches of industry and the national economy in general presupposes complete freedom of competition and the free flow of capital from one branch to another. However, the private ownership of land creates monopoly, which hinders that free flow. Because of that monopoly, the products of agriculture, where a lower organic composition of capital exists, and consequently an individually higher rate of profit, do not enter into the quite free process of the equalization of the rate of profit. As a monopolist, the landowner can keep the price above the average, and this monopoly price gives rise to absolute rent. Differential rent cannot be done away with under capitalism, but absolute rent can — for instance, by the nationalization of the land, by making it State property. That would undermine the monopoly of private landowners, and would mean the more consistent and full operation of freedom of competition in agriculture. That is why, as Marx points out, bourgeois radicals have again and again in the course of history advanced this progressive bourgeois demand for nationalization of the land, a demand which, however, frightens most of the bourgeoisie, because it would too closely affect another monopoly, one that is particularly important and «sensitive» today — the monopoly of the means of production in general. (A remarkably popular, concise, and clear exposition of his theory of the average rate of profit on capital and of absolute ground rent is given by Marx himself in a letter to Engels, dated the 2nd of August, 1862; also the letter of the 9th of August, 1862.)

#3.7. EVOLUTION OF CAPITALISM IN AGRICULTURE

With reference to the history of ground rent, it is also important to note Marx's analysis showing how labour-rent (the peasant creates surplus-product by working on the lord's land) is transformed into rent paid in products or in kind (the peasant creates surplus-product on their own land and hands it over to the landlord because of «non-economic constraint»), then into money-rent (rent in kind, which is converted into money — the obrok [quit-rent] of old Russia — as a result of the development of commodity production), and, finally, into capitalist rent, when the peasant is replaced by the agricultural entrepreneur, who cultivates the soil with the help of hired labour. In connection with this analysis of the «genesis of capitalist ground rent», note should be taken of a number of profound ideas (of particular importance to backward countries like Russia) expressed by Marx regarding the evolution of capitalism in agriculture:

The transformation of rent in kind into money-rent is furthermore not only inevitably accompanied, but even anticipated, by the formation of a class of propertyless day-labourers, who hire themselves out for money. During their genesis, when this new class appears but sporadically, the custom necessarily develops among the more prosperous peasants, subject to rent payments, of exploiting agricultural wage-labourers for their own account, much as in feudal times, when the more well-to-do peasant serfs themselves also held serfs. In this way, they gradually acquire the possibility of accumulating a certain amount of wealth and themselves becoming transformed into future capitalists. The old self-employed possessors of land themselves thus give rise to a nursery school for capitalist tenants, whose development is conditioned by the general development of capitalist production beyond the bounds of the countryside.17

The expropriation and eviction of a part of the agricultural population not only set free for industrial capital the labourers, their means of subsistence, and material for labour, it also created the home market.12

In their turn, the impoverishment and ruin of the rural population play a part in the creation, for capital, of a reserve army of labour. In every capitalist country, «part of the agricultural population is therefore constantly on the point of passing over into an urban or manufacturing [that is, non-agricultural] proletariat [...]. This source of relative surplus population is thus constantly flowing [...]. The agricultural labourer is therefore reduced to the minimum wage, and always stands with one foot already in the swamp of pauperism».12 The peasant's private ownership of the land they till is the basis of small-scale production and the condition for its prospering and achieving the classical form. But such small-scale production is compatible only with a narrow and primitive framework of production and society. Under capitalism, the «exploitation of the peasants differs only in form from the exploitation of the industrial proletariat. The exploiter is the same: capital. The individual capitalists exploit the individual peasants through mortgages and usury; the capitalist class exploits the peasant class through the State taxes».18 «The smallholding of the peasant is now only the pretext that allows the capitalist to draw profits, interest, and rent from the soil, while leaving it to the tiller of the soil themself to see how they can extract their wages.»19 As a rule, the peasant cedes to capitalist society, that is, to the capitalist class, even a part of the wages, sinking «to the level of the Irish tenant farmer — all under the pretence of being a private proprietor».18 What is «one of the reasons why grain prices are lower in countries with predominantly small-peasant land proprietorship than in countries with a capitalist mode of production»?17 It is that the peasant hands over for free to society (that is, the capitalist class) a part of their surplus-product. «This lower price [of grain and other agricultural products] is consequently a result of the producers' poverty and by no means of their labour productivity.»17 Under capitalism, the small-holding system, which is the normal form of small-scale production, deteriorates, collapses, and perishes. «Proprietorship of land parcels, by its very nature, excludes the development of social productive forces of labour, social forms of labour, social concentration of capital, large-scale cattle-raising, and the progressive application of science. Usury and a taxation system must impoverish it everywhere. The expenditure of capital in the price of the land withdraws this capital from cultivation. An infinite fragmentation of means of production, and isolation of the producers themselves.»17 (Cooperative societies, that is, associations of small peasants, while playing an extremely progressive bourgeois role, only weaken this tendency, without eliminating it; nor must it be forgotten that these cooperative societies do much for the well-to-do peasants, and very little — next to nothing — for the masses of poor peasants; then, the associations themselves become exploiters of hired labour.) «Monstrous waste of human energy. Progressive deterioration of conditions of production and increased prices of means of production — an inevitable law of proprietorship of parcels.»17 In agriculture, as in industry, capitalism transforms the process of production only at the price of the «martyrdom of the producer». «The dispersion of the rural labourers over larger areas breaks down their power of resistance, while concentration increases that of the town operatives. In modern agriculture, as in the urban industries, the increased productivity and quantity of the labour set in motion are bought at the cost of laying waste and consuming by disease labour-power itself. Moreover, all progress in capitalist agriculture is a progress in the art, not only of robbing the labourer, but of robbing the soil [...]. Capitalist production, therefore, develops technology, and the combination of various processes into a social whole, only by sapping the original sources of all wealth — the soil and the labourer.»12

#4. SOCIALISM

From the above, it is evident that Marx deduces the inevitability of the transformation of capitalist society into socialist society wholly and exclusively from the economic law of the development of modern society. The socialization of labour, which is advancing ever more rapidly in thousands of forms and has manifested itself very strikingly during the half-century since the death of Marx, in the growth of large-scale production, capitalist cartels, syndicates, and trusts, as well as in the gigantic increase in the dimensions and power of finance capital, provides the main material basis for the inevitable advent of socialism. The intellectual and moral motive force and the physical executor of this transformation is the proletariat, which has been trained by capitalism itself. The struggle of the proletariat against the bourgeoisie, which finds expression in a variety of forms ever richer in content, inevitable becomes a political struggle directed toward the conquest of political power by the proletariat («the dictatorship of the proletariat»). The socialization of production cannot but lead to the means of production becoming the property of society, to the «expropriation of the expropriators». A tremendous rise in labour productivity, a shorter workday, and the replacement of the remnants, the ruins, of small-scale, primitive, and disunited production by collective and improved labour — such are the direct consequences of this transformation. Capitalism breaks for all time the ties between agriculture and industry, but, at the same time, through its highest development, it prepares new elements of those ties, a union between industry and agriculture based on the conscious application of science and the concentration of productive labour, and on a redistribution of the human population (thus putting an end both to rural backwardness, isolation, and barbarism, and to the unnatural concentration of vast masses of people in big cities). A new form of family, new conditions in the status of women and in the upbringing of the younger generation are prepared by the highest forms of present-day capitalism: the labour of women and children and the breakup of the patriarchal family by capitalism inevitably assume the most terrible, disastrous, and repulsive forms in modern society. Nevertheless, «modern industry, by assigning, as it does, an important part in the socially organized process of production, outside the domestic sphere, to women, to young people, and to children regardless of gender, creates a new economic basis for a higher form of the family and of romantic and sexual relations. It is, of course, just as absurd to hold the Germanic-Christian form of the family to be absolute and final as it would be to apply that character to the Ancient Roman, the Ancient Greek, or the Eastern forms, which, moreover, taken together, form a series in historical development. Moreover, it is obvious that the fact of the collective working group being composed of individuals regardless of gender and age must necessarily, under suitable conditions, become a source of human development; although, in its spontaneously developed, brutal, capitalist form, where the labourer exists for the process of production, and not the process of production for the labourer, that fact is a pestiferous source of corruption and slavery».12 The factory system contains «the germ of the education of the future, an education that will, in the case of every child over a given age, combine productive labour with instruction and gymnastics, not only as one of the methods of adding to the efficiency of social production, but as the only method of producing fully developed human beings».12 Marx's Socialism places the problems of nationality and of the State on the same historical footing, not only in the sense of explaining the past, but also in the sense of a bold prediction of the future and of bold practical action for its achievement. Nations are an inevitable product, an inevitable form, in the bourgeois epoch of social development. The working class could not grow strong, become mature, and take shape without «constituting itself within the nation», without being «national» («though not in the bourgeois sense of the word»).15 The development of capitalism, however, breaks down national barriers more and more, does away with national seclusion, and substitutes class antagonisms for national antagonisms. It is, therefore, perfectly true of the developed capitalist countries that «the workers have no country» and that «united action» by the workers, of the developed countries at least, «is one of the first conditions for the emancipation of the proletariat».15 The State, which is organized coercion, inevitably came into being at a definite stage in the development of society, when the latter had split into irreconcilable classes, and could not exist without an «authority» ostensibly standing above society, and, to a certain degree, separate from society. Arising out of class contradictions, the State becomes «the State of the most powerful, economically dominant class, which, through the medium of the State, becomes also the politically dominant class, and thus acquires new means of holding down and exploiting the oppressed class. Thus, the State of antiquity was above all the State of the slave-owners for the purpose of holding down the slaves, as the feudal State was the body of the nobility for holding down the peasant serfs and bondspeople, and the modern representative State is an instrument of exploitation of wage-labour by capital»20 (from a work in which the writer expounds his own views and Marx's). Even the democratic republic, the freest and most progressive form of the bourgeois State, does not eliminate this fact in any way, but merely modifies its form (the links between the government and the stock exchange, the corruption — direct and indirect — of officialdom and the press, and so on). By leading to the abolition of classes, socialism will thereby lead to the abolition of the State as well. Engels writes:

The first act by virtue of which the State really constitutes itself the representative of the whole of society — the taking possession of the means of production in the name of society — this is, at the same time, its last independent act as a State. State interference in social relations becomes, in one domain after another, superfluous, and then dies out of itself; the government of persons is replaced by the administration of things, and by the conduct of processes of production. The State is not ‹abolished›. It dies out.7

Society, which will reorganise production on the basis of a free and equal association of the producers, will put the whole machinery of State where it will then belong: into the museum of antiquities, by the side of the spinning-wheel and the bronze axe.20

Finally, as regards the attitude of Marx's Socialism toward the small peasantry, which will continue to exist in the period of the expropriation of the expropriators, we must refer to a declaration made by Engels, which expresses Marx's views:

[...] when we are in possession of State power we shall not even think of forcibly expropriating the small peasants (whether with or without compensation), as we shall have to do in the case of the big landowners. Our task relative to the small peasant consists, in the first place, in effecting a transition of their private undertaking, private property to a co-operative one, not forcibly but by dint of example and the proffer of social assistance for this purpose. And then of course we shall have ample means of showing to the small peasant prospective advantages that must be obvious to them even today.21

#5. TACTICS OF THE CLASS STRUGGLE OF THE PROLETARIAT

After examining, as early as 1844-45, one of the main shortcomings in earlier materialism, namely, its inability to understand the conditions or appreciate the importance of practical revolutionary activity, Marx, along with his theoretical work, devoted unremitting attention, throughout his lifetime, to the tactical problems of the class struggle of the proletariat. An immense amount of material bearing on this is contained in all the works of Marx, particularly in the four volumes of his correspondence with Engels, published in 1913. This material is still far from having been brought together, collected, examined, and studied. We shall therefore have to confine ourselves here to the most general and brief remarks, emphasizing that Marx justly considered that, without this aspect, materialism is incomplete, one-sided, and lifeless. The fundamental task of proletarian tactics was defined by Marx in strict conformity with all the postulates of his materialist-dialectical Weltanschauung [worldview]. Only an objective consideration of the sum total of the relations between absolutely all the classes in a given society, and, consequently, a consideration of the objective stage of development reached by that society and of the relations between it and other societies, can serve as a basis for the correct tactics of a progressive class. At the same time, all classes and all countries are regarded, not statically, but dynamically, that is, not in a state of immobility, but in motion (whose laws are determined by the economic conditions of existence of each class). Motion, in its turn, is regarded from the standpoint, not only of the past, but also of the future, and that not in the vulgar sense in which it is understood by the «evolutionists», who see only slow changes, but dialectically. Marx wrote to Engels: «Only your small-minded German philistine who measures world history by the ell and by what he happens to think are ‹interesting news items›, could regard 20 years as more than a day where major developments of this kind are concerned, though these may be again succeeded by days into which 20 years are compressed.»22 At each stage of development, at each moment, proletarian tactics must take account of this objectively inevitable dialectic of human history, on the one hand, utilizing the periods of political stagnation or of sluggish, so-called «peaceful» development in order to develop the class-consciousness, strength, and militancy of the progressive class, and, on the other hand, directing all the work of this utilization toward the «final aim» of the advance of that class, toward creating in it the ability to find practical solutions for great tasks in the great days «into which 20 years are compressed».22 Two of Marx's arguments are of special importance in this connection: one of these is contained in The Poverty of Philosophy and concerns the economic struggle and economic organizations of the proletariat; the other is contained in the Communist Manifesto and concerns the political tasks of the proletariat. The former runs as follows:

Large-scale industry concentrates in one place a crowd of people unknown to each other. Competition divides their interests. But the maintenance of wages, this common interest which they have against their boss, unites them in a common thought of resistance — combination [...]. Combinations, at first isolated, constitute themselves into groups [...] and, in the face of always united capital, the maintenance of the association becomes more necessary to [the workers] than that of wages [...]. In this struggle — a veritable civil war — all the elements necessary for a coming battle unite and develop. Once it has reached this point, association takes on a political character.23

Here, we have the programme and tactics of the economic struggle and of the trade-union movement for several decades to come, for the whole lengthy period in which the proletariat will prepare its forces for the «coming battle». All this should be compared with numerous references by Marx and Engels to the example of the British labour movement, showing how industrial «prosperity» leads to attempts «to buy the proletariat»,24 to divert them from the struggle; how this prosperity in general «demoralizes the workers»;24 how the British proletariat becomes «bourgeoisified»«the ultimate aim of this most bourgeois of all nations would appear to be the possession, alongside the bourgeoisie, of a bourgeois aristocracy and a bourgeois proletariat»;24 how its «revolutionary energy»25 oozes away; how it will be necessary to wait a more or less lengthy period of time before «the English workers will throw off what seems to be a bourgeois contagion»;22 how the British labour movement «the mettle of the old Chartists»;26 how the British workers' leaders are becoming a type of «go-between for the radical bourgeoisie with the workers»27 (in reference to Holyoak); how, owing to Britain's monopoly, and as long as that monopoly lasts, «the British worker will not budge».28 The tactics of the economic struggle, in connection with the general course (and outcome) of the working-class movement, are considered here from a remarkably broad, comprehensive, dialectical, and genuinely revolutionary standpoint.

The Communist Manifesto advanced a fundamental Marxist principle on the tactics of the political struggle:

The Communists fight for the attainment of the immediate aims, for the enforcement of the momentary interests of the working class, but, in the movement of the present, they also represent and take care of the future of that movement.15

That was why, in 1848, Marx supported the political party of the «agrarian revolution» in Poland, «that political party which brought about the Cracow Uprising in 1846».15 In Germany, Marx, in 1848 and '49, supported the extreme revolutionary democrats, and, subsequently, never retracted what he had then said about tactics. He regarded the German bourgeoisie as an element which was, from the very beginning, «inclined to betray the people» (only an alliance with the peasantry could have enabled the bourgeoisie to completely achieve its aims) «and to compromise with the crowned representative of the old society».29 Here is Marx's summary of the class standpoint of the German bourgeoisie in the period of the bourgeois-democratic revolution — an analysis which, incidentally, is a sample of a materialism that examines society in motion, and, moreover, not only from the aspect of a motion that is backward:

Without faith in itself, without faith in the people, grumbling at those above, trembling before those below [...] intimidated by the world storm [...] no energy in any respect [...] plagiarism in every respect [...] without initiative [...] an abominable dotard finding himself condemned to lead and to mislead the first youthful impulses of a virile people so as to make them serve his own senile interests [...].29

About 20 years later, Marx declared, in a letter to Engels, that the Revolution of 1848 had failed because the bourgeoisie had preferred peace with slavery to the mere prospect of a struggle for freedom. When the revolutionary period of 1848-49 ended, Marx opposed any attempt to play at revolution (his struggle against Schapper and Willich), and insisted on the ability to work in the new phase, which, in a quasi-«peaceful» way, was preparing new revolutions. The spirit in which Marx wanted this work to be conducted is to be seen in his appraisal of the situation in Germany in 1856, the darkest period of reaction: «The whole thing in Germany will depend on whether it is possible to back the proletarian revolution by some second edition of the Peasant War, in which case the affair should go swimmingly.»1 While the democratic (bourgeois) revolution in Germany was uncompleted, Marx focused every attention, in the tactics of the Socialist proletariat, on developing the democratic energy of the peasantry. He held that Lassalle's attitude was «objectively [...] the betrayal of the whole workers' movement to the Prussians»,30 incidentally because Lassalle was tolerant of the Junkers and Prussian nationalism. Engels wrote in 1865, in exchanging views with Marx on their upcoming joint declaration in the press:

In a predominantly agricultural country [...] it is despicable to attack only the bourgeoisie in the name of the industrial proletariat, without even mentioning the brutal patriarchal exploitation of the rural proletariat by the big feudal aristocracy.31

From 1864 to '70, when the period of the consummation of the bourgeois-democratic revolution in Germany was coming to an end, a period in which the Prussian and Austrian exploiting classes were contending to complete that revolution in one way or another from above, Marx not only rebuked Lassalle, who was coquetting with Bismarck, but also corrected Liebknecht, who had lapsed into «Austrophilia»32 and a defence of particularism; Marx demanded revolutionary tactics which would combat with equal ruthlessness both Bismarck and the Austrophiles, tactics which would not be adapted to the «victor» — the Prussian Junker — but would immediately renew the revolutionary struggle against them, also in the conditions created by the Prussian military victories. In the celebrated Address of the International of the 9th of September, 1870, Marx warned the French proletariat against an untimely uprising, but, when an uprising nevertheless took place (1871), Marx enthusiastically hailed the revolutionary initiative of the masses, who were «storming the heavens».33 From the standpoint of Marx's dialectical materialism, the defeat of revolutionary action in that situation, as in many others, was a lesser evil, in the general course and outcome of the proletarian struggle, than the abandonment of a position already occupied, than surrender without battle. Such a surrender would have demoralized the proletariat and weakened its militancy. While fully appreciating the use of legal means of struggle during periods of political stagnation and the domination of bourgeois legality, Marx, in 1877 and '78, following the passage of the Anti-Socialist Law, sharply condemned Most's «revolutionary jargon»;34 no less sharply, if not more so, did he attack the opportunism that had, for a time, come over the official Social-Democratic Party, which did not at once display resoluteness, firmness, revolutionary spirit, and a readiness to resort to an underground struggle in response to the Anti-Socialist Law.


#Workers and oppressed people of the world, unite!

#BIBLIOGRAPHY OF MARXISM

#Nikolaj Lenin
#July-November 1914

#

No complete collection of Marx's works and letters has yet been published.35 More works by Marx have been translated into Russian than into any other language. The following list of Marx's writings is arranged in chronological order:

  • In 1841, Marx wrote his thesis on Epicurus's philosophy. In this thesis, Marx still fully adhered to the Hegelian idealist standpoint.
  • In 1842, Marx wrote articles for the Rhenish Newspaper (Cologne), among them a criticism of the free-press debate in the Sixth Rhenish Diet, an article on the laws concerning the theft of timber, another in defence of divorcing politics from theology, and so on. Here, we see signs of Marx's transition from idealism to materialism and from revolutionary democracy to Communism.
  • In 1844, under the editorship of Marx and Arnold Ruge, there appeared, in Paris, the German-French Yearbooks, in which this transition was finally made. Among Marx's articles published in that magazine, the most noteworthy are A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right and On the Jewish Question.
  • In 1845, Marx and Engels jointly published, in Frankfort-on-the-Main, a pamphlet entitled The Holy Family.
  • In the spring of 1845, Marx wrote his Theses on Feuerbach (published as an appendix to Friedrich Engels's pamphlet entitled Ludwig Feuerbach).
  • In 1845-47, Marx wrote a number of articles (most of which have not been collected, republished, or translated into Russian in the papers Vorwärts [Forward], Deutsche-Brüsseler-Zeitung [German Brussels Newspaper] (1847); Westphälisches Dampfboot [Westphalian Steamboat] (Elberfeld, 1845-48); and Der Gesellschaftsspiegel [The Social Mirror] (Elberfeld, 1846).
  • In 1847, Marx wrote his fundamental work against Proudhon, The Poverty of Philosophy. The book was published in Brussels and Paris.
  • In 1848, On Free Trade was published in Brussels, followed by the publication, in London, in collaboration with Friedrich Engels, of the celebrated Manifesto of the Communist Party, which has been translated into probably all the languages of Europe and into a number of other languages.
  • From the 1st of June, 1848 to the 19th of May, 1849, the New Rhenish Newspaper was published in Cologne with Marx as the actual editor-in-chief. His numerous articles for that paper, which to this very day remains the finest and unsurpassed organ of the revolutionary proletariat, have not been collected and republished in full. Wage-Labour and Capital, published in that paper, has been repeatedly issued as a pamphlet; also from the same paper, The Liberals at the Helm.
  • In 1849, Marx published, in Cologne, Two Political Trials (two speeches in his own defence by Marx, who was acquitted by a jury when facing trial on the charge of having violated the press law and called for armed resistance to the government).
  • In 1850, Marx published, in Hamburg, six issues of the New Rhenish Newspaper magazine. Especially noteworthy are Marx's articles, republished by Engels in 1895 in a pamphlet entitled The Class Struggles in France, 1848-50.
  • In 1852, a pamphlet by Marx was published in New York under the title of The 18th Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte.
  • In the same year, a pamphlet was published in London under the title of Revelations on the Cologne Communist Trial.
  • From August 1851 to 1862, Marx was a regular contributor to the New York Tribune, where many of his articles appeared unsigned, as editorials. Most outstanding among these is a series of articles, Revolution and Counter-Revolution in Germany, which were republished after the death of Marx and Engels.36 Some of Marx's articles in the Tribune were later published in London as separate pamphlets, as, for instance, the one on Palmerston, published in 1856; Revelations of the Diplomatic History of the 18th Century (regarding the constant venal dependence on Russia of the British Liberal ministers); and others. After Marx's death, his daughter, Eleanor Marx-Aveling, published a number of his Tribune articles on the Eastern question, under the title of The Eastern Question.
  • From the end of 1854, and during 1855, Marx contributed to the Neue Oder-Zeitung [New Oder Newspaper] and in 1861-62 to the Viennese paper Press. These articles have not been collected, and only a few of them were reprinted in Die neue Zeit [New Times], as were also Marx's numerous letters. The same is true about Marx's articles from Das Volk [The People] (London, 1859) on the diplomatic history of the Italian War of 1859.
  • In 1859, Marx's A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy appeared in Berlin.
  • In 1860, a pamphlet by Marx, entitled Mr. Vogt, appeared in London.
  • In 1864, the Inaugural Address of the International Workers' Association, which was written by Marx, came out in London. Marx was the author of numerous manifestos, appeals, and resolutions of the General Council of the International. This material is far from having been analysed or even collected. The first approach to this work is Gustav Jaeckh's book, The International, which includes several of Marx's letters and draft resolutions.
  • Among the documents of the International that Marx wrote was the Address of the General Council on the Paris Commune. The document appeared in 1871 in London, as a pamphlet entitled The Civil War in France.
  • Between 1862 and '74, Marx corresponded with Kugelmann, a member of the International.
  • In 1867, Marx's main work, Capital, Volume 1, appeared in Hamburg. Volumes 2 and 3 were published by Engels in 1885 and '94, after the death of Marx.
  • In 1876, Marx took part in the writing of Engels's Anti-Dühring; he went over the manuscript of the whole work and wrote an entire chapter dealing with the history of political economy.

The following works by Marx were published posthumously:

  • Critique of the Gotha Programme.
  • Value, Price, and Profit (a lecture delivered in June 1865).
  • From the Literary Remains of Karl Marx, Friedrich Engels, and Ferdinand Lassalle. Lassalle's letters to Marx, published separately, are included.
  • Letters from Karl Marx, Friedrich Engels, and Others to F.A. Sorge and Others.
  • Theories of Surplus Value, three volumes in four parts, Stuttgart, 1905-10, which is the manuscript of Volume 4 of Capital and published by Kautsky.
  • In 1913, four big volumes of the Marx-Engels Correspondence came out in Stuttgart, with 1'386 letters written between September 1844 and the 10th of January, 1883, and providing a mass of highly valuable material for a study of Marx's biography and views.
  • In 1917, two volumes of Marx's and Engels's works appeared, containing their articles from 1852-62 (in German).

This list of Marx's works must conclude with a note that many of Marx's shorter articles and letters, published, for the most part, in New Times, Forward, and other German-language Social-Democratic periodicals, have not been enumerated.

The literature on Marx and Marxism is very extensive. We shall mention only what is most outstanding, and divide the authors into three main groups:

  • Firstly, Marxists who, in important matters, adhere to Marx's standpoint.
  • Secondly, bourgeois writers, in essence hostile to Marxism.
  • Thirdly, revisionists who, while claiming to accept certain fundamentals of Marxism, in fact replace it with bourgeois conceptions. The Populist attitude toward Marx should be considered a peculiarly Russian variety of revisionism.

For a correct appraisal of Marx's views, an acquaintance is essential with the works of Friedrich Engels, his closest fellow-thinker and collaborator. It is impossible to understand Marxism and to propound it fully without taking into account all the works of Engels.


  1. Source: Karl Marx: Letter to Friedrich Engels (16th of April, 1856) 

  2. Source: Friedrich Engels: Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy (Early 1886) 

  3. Source: Karl Marx: Letter to Arnold Ruge (September 1843) 

  4. Source: Karl Marx: Preface to the 1844 German Edition of A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right (End of 1843-January 1844) 

  5. Source: Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels: The Holy Family (September-November 1844) 

  6. Source: Karl Marx: Postface to the 1873 German Edition of Capital, Vol. 1 (24th of January, 1873) 

  7. Source: Friedrich Engels: Anti-Dühring (September 1876-June 1878) 

  8. Source: Karl Marx: Letter to Friedrich Engels (12th of December, 1868) 

  9. Source: Karl Marx: Theses on Feuerbach (April 1845) 

  10. Source: Friedrich Engels: Preface to the 1885 German Edition of Anti-Dühring (23rd of September, 1885) 

  11. Source: Karl Marx: Letter to Friedrich Engels (8th of January, 1868) 

  12. Source: Karl Marx: Capital, Vol. 1 (Before September 1867) 

  13. Source: Karl Marx: Preface to the 1859 German Edition of A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (January 1859) 

  14. Source: Karl Marx: Letter to Friedrich Engels (7th of July, 1866) 

  15. Source: Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels: Manifesto of the Communist Party (November 1847-January 1848) 

  16. Source: Karl Marx: Preface to the 1867 German Edition of Capital, Vol. 1 (25th of July, 1867) 

  17. Source: Karl Marx: Capital, Vol. 3 (1863-83) 

  18. Source: Karl Marx: The Class Struggles in France, 1848-50 (January-November 1850) 

  19. Source: Karl Marx: The 18th Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (December 1851-March 1852) 

  20. Source: Friedrich Engels: The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State (April-May 1884) 

  21. Source: Friedrich Engels: The Peasant Question in France and Germany (15th to 22nd of November, 1894) 

  22. Source: Karl Marx: Letter to Friedrich Engels (9th of April, 1863) 

  23. Source: Karl Marx: The Poverty of Philosophy (First Half of 1847) 

  24. Source: Friedrich Engels: Letter to Karl Marx (7th of October, 1858) 

  25. Source: Friedrich Engels: Letter to Karl Marx (8th of April, 1863) 

  26. Source: Karl Marx: Letter to Friedrich Engels (2nd of April, 1866) 

  27. Source: Friedrich Engels: Letter to Karl Marx (19th of November, 1869) 

  28. Source: Unknown 

  29. Source: Karl Marx: The Bourgeoisie and the Counter-Revolution (December 1848) 

  30. Source: Friedrich Engels: Letter to Karl Marx (27th of January, 1865) 

  31. Source: Friedrich Engels: Letter to Karl Marx (5th of February, 1865) 

  32. Source: Unknown 

  33. Source: Karl Marx: Letter to Ludwig Kugelmann (12th of April, 1871) 

  34. Source: Karl Marx: Letter to F.A. Sorge (19th of September, 1879) 

  35. Editor's Note: Today, the best available collections are the Collected Works of Marx and Engels, published by Lawrence & Wishart, and the Marx-Engels Gesamtausgabe, published by Walter de Gruyter. 

  36. Editor's Note: The work Revolution and Counter-Revolution in Germany was actually written by Engels in Marx's name.